Of course there's nothing very new about this problem, nor is it, at first glance, a matter of much controversy. After all, many, many significant ideas from the past--from the ether to George Fitzhugh's defense of slavery--are both intellectually significant and, from the standpoint of the twenty-first century, deeply incorrect. Yet we have no problem taking them seriously and writing about or teaching them.
But the issue is made more vexed if the ideas in question are living ideas. If--despite their being wrong or worse--they have advocates today. And this is frequently the case when one studies contemporary intellectual history.
Here are just some of the instances in which this issue has come up on this blog in recent months: David's coverage of the dustup between Jill Lepore and Gordon Wood over how to treat the Teaparty's view of the American past; Andrew's discussion of the attack on ethnic studies in Arizona; Mike's consideration of Mike Huckabee's bizarre denial of British imperialism; and the discussion of Andrew's post on Lisa Szefel's review of Dan Rodgers's Age of Fracture.
As the title of this post suggests, I'm really only going to pull briefly on this conversational thread, as I need to get back to grading and I'm not sure a longer post would produce any answers in any event. But as this issue keeps coming up, I figured I'd call attention to it and make a few observations:
1) Historians' truth-squadding has its place. People do express opinions about the past that are simply wrong. And as historians, we have a responsibility, perhaps even a duty, to point out when people use bad history to bolster their arguments in public debate. But while pointing out when people simply get the past wrong is an important thing that we historians can do, it's a very small part of what doing (contemporary) history, let alone (contemporary) intellectual history, consists of.
2) Part of doing intellectual history well consists of taking nearly every idea seriously. The limits to this rule involve some measure of significance. And they also, in my opinion, exclude the rare idea that is expressed in utterly bad faith. But significant ideas that we happen to believe are wrong, inane, or even deeply evil should still be taken seriously. One of the books I like using in my course on the history and memory of World War II since 1945 is Inga Clendinnen's Reading the Holocaust. Among other things, Clendinnen argues that historians must take Nazi ideas seriously:
One of my early difficulties in grasping what the Nazis thought they were up to was that I could not take their professed racist ideology seriously. Instead of listening hard to what they were saying, I assumed the language to be largely rhetorical. That is a natural but completely misleading response. Other people do think differently from us. (p. 91)Of course the Nazis are a particularly hard case in this regard. But what Clendinnen (rightly IMO) says about them should also be said of others who we encounter in our studies whose ideas strike us (presumably to a lesser extent than the Nazis') as erroneous, foolish, or vicious. We should resist the urge to simply "translate" uncomfortable ideas into terms that more easily make sense to us. We should be wary of too easily denying that the people we study believe what they say they believe.
3) Of course how we do this--what tools we use, to borrow the metaphor from the discussion of Szefel's review of Age of Fracture--is a more complicated question.
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar